A realm of freedom

It seems that if the goal of a people is to create a thriving society, it is very sensible for it to have a state with a constitution that has a bill of rights that is very carefully thought out with the goal of perpetuating liberty in mind, since comparatively free societies would seem to tend to be relatively thriving. It is, of course, necessary for a state that guarantees basic rights and liberties in such a way to be fairly prosocial as a whole in order for the society in which it exists to do well, and it seems that it might be possible to build a state that is considerably more prosocial than what have existed so far, and in order for a state to achieve this level of prosociality, it should in my opinion also have the features described below in addition to a number of others:

The state should be a federal elective constitutional monarchy with a dual-executive system and a bicameral parliament. The monarch should be elected directly with a two-round system, and they should be dethronable by electing a replacement. The realm should also have a lieutenant monarch who should be elected alongside the monarch in normal elections, and candidates for lieutenant monarch should be chosen by the candidates for monarch at least one hundred days before monarchical elections. The monarch and the lieutenant monarch should not be allowed to be members of political parties. Monarchical elections should be callable with initiatives signed by some reasonable percentage of the electorate, but it should normally not be possible to call a monarchical election with such an initiative within some sensible length of time from the previous successful initiative to call a monarchical election. The monarch and both chambers of the parliament should also be able to call monarchical elections, but the latter should be able to call them only as frequently as the electorate. Whenever a monarchical election is called, it should be held within a year. As the monarch would be elected and also dethronable with direct elections, it seems fairly reasonable for them to have rather significant powers.
The candidate for head of government should normally be nominated by the lower chamber of the parliament, but it should also be able to delegate nominating the candidate to the monarch. The candidate for head of government should then naturally form a potential cabinet, and it should, of course, need to receive a vote of confidence from the lower chamber in order to become a governing cabinet, and if it doesn’t receive a vote of confidence, the potential cabinet should be dissolved, and the process should naturally start over. The lower chamber should, of course, be able to dismiss the cabinet at any time by passing a motion of no confidence. The head of government should be able to present a motion of confidence to the lower chamber, and if it does not pass, the cabinet should be dismissed. If the cabinet is dismissed, the monarch should be able to appoint a caretaker cabinet composed of independents.
The presiding officer of the lower chamber should be elected by its members, and nominating a candidate for presiding officer should require at least ten members including at least three with a different party affiliation than the candidate. The presiding officer should not be allowed to be a member of any political party. The lieutenant monarch should be the presiding officer of the upper chamber. Neither presiding officer should be able to cast votes in the chambers over which they preside, except to break ties. Both chambers should have to appoint a member as a lieutenant presiding officer who would naturally be the acting presiding officer whenever their presiding officer is absent. Only the actual presiding officers should be able to cast tie-breaking votes, but acting presiding officers should, of course, be able to vote normally.
Members of both chambers of the parliament should be able to introduce bills, and both chambers should be able to amend bills passed by the other chamber. The electoral term of the lower chamber should be five years, and the electoral term of the upper chamber should be ten years.
The electorate should be able to call early elections to both chambers of the parliament with initiatives, but it should not be possible to call early elections to both chambers with a single initiative. The head of government should be able to call an early election to the lower chamber of the parliament at any time, and an early election to the upper chamber should be held if a simple majority of it votes in favour of calling one.
Changing the constitution should require two successive lower chambers of the parliament, the upper chamber of the parliament, and the electorate voting in favour of the proposed change with two-thirds majorities, in that order.

There should be multiple independent election commissions, and they should perhaps be considered to be a separate branch of government. Ten seems like a suitable amount of commissioners per commission, and the commissioners should be appointed for ten year terms, and they should continue serving after the ends of their terms until they are replaced. They should not be allowed to be members of parties nor otherwise clearly affiliated with parties.
Commissioner candidates should normally be nominated by the monarch, and they should be approved by two thirds of the upper chamber of the parliament in order to be appointed. It should be possible to appoint only a single commissioner to each commission per year, except when a commissioner resigns or dies, in which case it should also be possible to also appoint a replacement for the remainder of the term of the commissioner who resigned or died.
The commissions should be initially composed of acting commissioners, and these acting commissioners should be chosen by lottery from a public pool of volunteers approved by the monarch and the parliament. The acting commissioners should then be replaced by commissioners appointed with the normal procedure, and each time a commissioner is appointed to a commission, the acting commissioner to be replaced in it should be chosen by lottery if there are at least two acting commissioners in the commission in question, naturally.

Depending on the type of election, each partaking party/electoral alliance or candidate should be allowed to appoint scrutineers, but there should naturally also be a cap on the number of scrutineers appointed by each partaking party/alliance or candidate, perhaps up to two per polling booth, and they should be appointed, for example, at least ten days before elections.
Election officials should be paid fairly for their work, and the amounts they would be paid should also be tied to the cost-of-living index.

The supreme court should have the power to strike down statutes and parts of statutes it deems unconstitutional. Judges’ appointments to all federal courts should be for indefinite terms, the candidates should be nominated by the monarch, and for a candidate to be appointed, at least two thirds of the upper chamber of the parliament should have to vote in favour of appointing them. Every candidate should be voted on separately. Judges should not have a set retirement age, and the constitution should clearly forbid setting one. The number of positions in the supreme court should be odd and set in the constitution: nine and eleven seem like the most reasonable options. The supreme court should be able to appoint temporary investigative committees, and the members of these committees should be able to investigate whatever the court tells them to investigate much like police officers. The supreme court should also have the right to order election audits and to make rulings on the outcomes of elections based on the results of such audits.

Both chambers of the parliament should also be able to appoint temporary investigative committees, and both chambers should be able to issue subpoenas to compel to produce evidence to be used in parliamentary hearings and to compel witnesses to testify in such hearings. Ignoring a parliamentary subpoena should be a felony for which the punishment should be a fine and one to ten years of imprisonment. Investigative committees appointed by the chambers of the parliament should also be able to issue subpoenas, and subpoenas issued by them should be considered parliamentary subpoenas.

The monarch should have the right to grant respites, reprieves, and pardons and to commute and remit sentences, both conditionally and unconditionally, but they should not be able to use this right pre-emptively. This right should only apply to convictions under federal law. It should also be automatically suspended if a monarchical election has been called and remain suspended until the results of the election have been verified, or until the monarch-elect has been coronated if the incumbent loses the election. The parliament should be able to grant amnesties for violations of federal law.

It might be best for the primary investigative federal police service to also be the federal security intelligence service. Alongside a service of this kind there should be a federal military police service, i.e. a gendarmerie that should also be the border security force, and these services should naturally assist each other whenever necessary. The general idea is, of course, to make federal internal security work fairly efficient, but such services should naturally have ample and well thought out supervision. The rest of the armed forces and the foreign intelligence service should, of course, have such supervision too. Thus, the primary federal investigative police and security intelligence service, the foreign intelligence service, the gendarmerie, and the rest of the federal armed forces should be supervised by the monarch, the lieutenant monarch, both chambers of the parliament (primarily via internal affairs committees), the head of government, people appointed for the purpose by the monarch, directly elected people with no other official duties, and independent supervision commissions (three or more supervising the investigative police and security intelligence service, at least two supervising the foreign intelligence service, two or more supervising the gendarmerie, and at least three supervising the rest of the federal armed forces) in addition to the ministries that they are subordinate to, of course. All of the supervision commissions should have ten commissioners, and the supervision commissioners should be appointed one at a time by the parliament with two-thirds majorities. The commissioners should serve ten year terms, and only one should be appointed to each commission per year, except when a commissioner resigns or dies, in which case it should also be possible to also appoint a replacement for the remainder of the term of the commissioner who resigned or died. The commissions should start with acting commissioners chosen by lottery, and the acting commissioners should then be replaced by commissioners appointed with the normal procedure, and each time a commissioner is appointed to a commission, the acting commissioner to be replaced should be chosen by lottery if there are at least two acting commissioners in the commission.

All law enforcement, intelligence, and military personnel should be forbidden from being members of political parties, except when necessary during intelligence gathering activities and criminal investigations, of course, and the punishments for violating this ban should be fairly severe; quasi-membership, i.e. connections to political parties comparable to those of members should, of course, also be punishable. Simply forbidding everyone in the public sector, except members of legislatures, their assistants, the members of the cabinet/federal executive council and the executive councils of the intrarealm polities’ legislatures, and the assistants of the members of the executive councils from being members and quasi-members of political parties seems like a fairly reasonable solution too.

All directly elected public officials should be removable from their offices by electing replacements for them. All federal public servants, except election commissioners, judges, members of investigative committees appointed by the supreme court, supervision commissioners, and members of investigative committees appointed by the parliament should be accountable to the monarch, and the monarch should be able to subject federal public servants, with the aforementioned exceptions, to a number of disciplinary measures: the monarch should be able to officially reprimand them in a public manner, demote them, reduce their pay by half or less for up to ten years, put them on unpaid leave for a fixed period of time or indefinitely, to dismiss them, and to partially or fully deny them pensions they would normally be entitled to as a result of working as federal public servants, and the monarch should, of course, also be able to reverse and change such punishments. The monarch should also have the right to ban people from being federal public servants for a given term or indefinitely and naturally also the right to remove such bans. The assistants of the members of the parliament and the cabinet should naturally not be considered public servants. These disciplinary powers and the right to ban people from being federal public servants should be automatically suspended if a monarchical election has been called, and stay suspended at least until the election results have been verified, or until the monarch-elect has been coronated if the incumbent loses the election.
Both chambers of the parliament should, of course, also have disciplinary powers, but they should more extensive than those of the monarch: both chambers should be able to subject all federal public servants to the disciplinary measures described above, but doing so to judges, election commissioners, supervision commissioners, and members of investigative commissions appointed by the supreme court should require two-thirds majorities if the monarch does not object to doing so and four fifths majorities if they do. Both chambers of the parliament should naturally also be able to ban people from being federal public servants and to remove such bans.
It seems that disciplinary powers like these would serve as fairly decent incentives for federal public servants to be relatively keen to, well, serve the public and also act appropriately towards other public servants, or in other words, as strong deterrents against non-, mis-, and malfeasance as well as other types of obviously inappropriate behaviour by federal public servants. The use of these disciplinary powers should, of course, be made public without exception via an official newspaper, of which there should naturally also be an online edition.

The monarch should be able to veto bills passed by the parliament, but the parliament should be able to override vetoes with two-thirds majorities. The monarch should also have the right to introduce bills to the parliament in order for them to have at least some ability to sidestep parliamentary deadlocks, or in other words, essentially to ”rule by prestige” in this way as necessary, and they should also have a right to call both advisory and binding referendums about issues and bills as a backup right. If the monarch has these rights, it would seem fairly sensible to have a parliament elected with a system of representation that is as fully proportional as reasonably possible: such a system seems like the most appropriate option, as it would be relatively respectful of the will of the voters, especially in comparison to pure first-past-the-post systems, which are often defended with claims that they typically produce functional cabinets due to only one party or a coalition of two parties usually having the majority of the seats in the parliament, which obviously is at least somewhat true, but equally obviously also very unideal in the sense that a very large proportion of the votes cast in parliamentary elections essentially does not matter in such systems, which is rather clearly quite the deficiency in a democracy.
Having just a single constituency for the federal parliament would also seem to be the most appropriate option: with a single realm-wide constituency the problem of hidden electoral thresholds would be neatly avoided, and if this is combined with an open-list system, elections would, of course, also be less about voting for parties and more about voting for specific candidates, and considering that the primary duty of the parliament of the realm would be to take care of matters concerning the entire realm, having only a single constituency for the federal parliament seems rather sensible indeed.
Independent candidates could, of course, also run in a system like this, but all candidates should, however, naturally be on an electoral list of some kind. If a list gets enough votes for more people to be elected from it than there are people on the list, the surplus seats should simply be left unfilled.

Establishing a system of direct democracy alongside representative democracy should be seriously considered, since it seems that direct democracy can be another fairly effective way of safeguarding the interests of the electorate. It can, of course, be somewhat problematic too if the electorate votes against the public interest due to, for example, good intentions combined with ignorance. If the electorate can elect at least somewhat enlightened and competent monarchs, and if the monarchs have reasonably considerable powers, having a system of direct democracy alongside representative democracy does not seem absolutely necessary from the public interest point of view, but it might be best to have a system of direct democracy too if the average voter is relatively capable of making informed voting decisions.

The monarch should be able to make the lieutenant monarch regent for an indefinite length of time by notifying the parliament about the matter via the presiding officer of the lower chamber of the parliament and the lieutenant presiding officer of the upper chamber of the parliament, and if they have done so, they should be able to resume reigning at any time in the same way.
If the position of lieutenant monarch becomes vacant, the monarch should be obligated to appoint an acting replacement within ten days of the position becoming vacant, and the person in question should also automatically become a candidate for lieutenant monarch, and them becoming lieutenant monarch should be subject to approval by the electorate. This replacement process should take place within a hundred days from the position becoming vacant, and if the electorate rejects the nominee, the process should start over.
If the monarch does not appoint an acting lieutenant monarch within ten days of the of start of the replacement process, the person who would normally be second in the line of succession should become acting lieutenant monarch, and a monarchical election should be automatically called. The presiding officer of the lower chamber of the parliament should be second in the line of succession, and they should be followed in it by the lieutenant presiding officer of the upper chamber, the head of government, the second most senior cabinet member, and so forth. The line of succession should also include at least all members of the parliament in order of seniority (determined by how long they have been members of the parliament), and there should also be a designated-survivor system.
If the monarch or regent is clearly unable to reign and communicate, i.e. obviously incapacitated or if they are missing and they have not made the lieutenant monarch or acting lieutenant monarch regent before becoming incapacitated or going missing, the lieutenant monarch or acting lieutenant monarch should become regent automatically, and the monarch or previous regent should be able to resume reigning in the normal manner described above. If the monarch or regent is incapacitated or missing and there is no lieutenant monarch nor acting lieutenant monarch, or if both the monarch/regent and the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch are incapacitated or missing, the first person in the line of succession who is capable of reigning and willing to reign should become regent, but the monarch or previous regent should be able to resume reigning in the normal manner, and if they resume reigning, the person who was regent before that should naturally become acting lieutenant monarch and allowed to remain in the position until the monarch appoints one, but if the monarch does not appoint an acting lieutenant monarch within ten days of the the position of lieutenant monarch becoming vacant, a monarchical election should be called, and if the monarch has not resumed reigning, the regent should be allowed remain regent until a monarch-elect is coronated.
Only the lieutenant monarch should be able to become monarch upon the throne becoming vacant, and if there is no lieutenant monarch when the throne becomes vacant, a monarchical election should be held within a year, and the throne and the position of lieutenant monarch should naturally be filled with acting occupants until the monarch-elect is coronated.
If a monarch-elect declines to be coronated or dies before they are coronated, the lieutenant monarch-elect should be coronated as monarch, and if the lieutenant monarch-elect cannot be coronated either, a new monarchical election should be held within a year, and the throne and the position of lieutenant monarch should, of course, be filled with acting occupants until the coronation.
If a majority of the cabinet and the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch declare to both chambers of the parliament in writing via the presiding officer of the lower chamber of the parliament and the lieutenant presiding officer of the upper chamber of the parliament that the monarch is unable to reign, the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch should become regent. If the monarch thereafter declares to both chambers of the parliament that they are not unable to reign, they should be able to resume reigning in ten days if the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch and a majority of the cabinet do not declare to both chambers of the parliament that the monarch is unable to reign within the ten days following the monarch declaring that they are not unable to reign, but if the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch and a majority of the cabinet make such a declaration, the parliament should vote on the matter, and if two thirds of both chambers of the parliament vote in favour of declaring the monarch unable to reign, the lieutenant monarch/acting lieutenant monarch should remain regent, and a monarchical election should be held within a year.
The monarch should be able to swap positions with the lieutenant monarch by giving a formal notification about the matter to both chambers of the parliament, both in writing and in person and then making an official televised announcement about it. Both abdicating and resigning from the position of lieutenant monarch should require a similar procedure.
If the lieutenant monarch becomes the monarch, both chambers of the parliament and the electorate should be able to call a monarchical election right away.

Duchy, county, and barony seem like suitable terms for the first-, second-, and third-level intrarealm polities, and their heads and lieutenant heads should have corresponding titles. Counties bordering other sovereign states should perhaps be called marches.
Baronies should be the municipal level of administration. Coextensive intrarealm polities should naturally be combined, but it seems best to avoid cities being first level intrarealm polities so that they would be more in touch and better integrated with the areas surrounding them, and vice versa.
It should be possible for counties and baronies to be parts of the federation directly, and it seems that special county and special barony would be at least sufficiently suitable terms for such intrarealm polities, and that special intrarealm polities would be an at least somewhat reasonable term for them collectively.
If an intrarealm polity has had less than 250 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should not be able to be a duchy, and if a county has less than 50 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should automatically become a barony. Baronies should have at least 10 000 inhabitants, and if a barony has less than 10 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should have to merge with another barony. If the population of a duchy is less than 250 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should automatically become a special county, and if a special county has less than 50 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should automatically become a special barony. If a special county has more than 250 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should automatically become a duchy, and if a special barony has more than 50 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, it should automatically become a special county.
Islands and island groups of the realm that are not parts of duchies, counties, nor baronies should be called separate island territories, for example, and they should be administered directly by the federal government, and if a separate island territory has had more than 10 000 inhabitants for ten years in a row, the parliament should be able to establish a special barony to govern it.

There should be five classes of duchies and corresponding classes of citizenship, and special intrarealm polities, separate island territories, and their citizens should naturally be classified similarly and be subject to similar rules:
Duchies of classes one and two should start with standardized constitutions and other laws largely similar to those of the federation. The roles of the executives and the legislatures of the duchies of these classes within said duchies would thus naturally be roughly comparable to what the roles of the executives and the parliament are at the federal level, and the roles of the executives and the legislatures of the counties of the duchies of these classes within said counties should be roughly similar to what the roles of the executives and the legislatures are at the duchy level, and this same general principle should also apply to their baronies.
Class one duchies should naturally comprise a free-travel area, and their citizens should also be class one citizens of the federation. Only class one citizens should be allowed to vote in federal elections, hold elected federal office, become members of the federal civil service, and serve in the federal armed forces. Class one citizens should be free to move into any duchy in the federation, and they should automatically become permanent residents of the duchies into which they move. Class one citizens who move into class one duchies should, of course, automatically also become citizens of the class one duchies they become residents of. Citizens of other classes should normally need visas for interduchy travel, and all non-class one citizens should be able to apply for both temporary and permanent residency in all duchies of the federation. A permanent resident should be eligible for citizenship if they have been a permanent resident for at least five years and have been physically residing in the duchy in question for at least four of the preceding five years. If a citizen is a permanent resident in a duchy, they should be able to vote in the intraduchy elections of the duchy in which they reside, and they should not be able to vote in the intraduchy elections of any other duchy. Citizens should naturally not be able to be citizens of multiple duchies simultaneously.
Class two duchies should have reasonably well-guarded interduchy borders, and they should be able to allow visa-free entry for citizens of other class two duchies.
The interduchy borders of class three duchies should naturally be more heavily guarded than those of class two duchies. Class three duchies should also be able to control some or all of their intercounty borders indefinitely. Their heads and lieutenant heads should be appointed by the monarch for indefinite terms, and the other members of their duchy-level administrations should be appointed by their heads, and the heads should be considered to be federal public servants. The heads of these duchies should also be able to officially reprimand the duchy-level public servants of their duchies in a public manner, demote them, reduce their pay by half or less for up to a year at a time, put them on unpaid leave for up to a year at a time, and to dismiss them; these disciplinary measures should, of course, be fully reversible and the punishments should naturally be also modifiable. Their counties and baronies should function in a similar way as the counties and the baronies of class one and class two duchies.
Class four duchies should have better-guarded interduchy borders than class three duchies, and traveling within them should be indefinitely controllable even between baronies. Their heads and lieutenant heads should, of course, also be appointed by the monarch for indefinite terms and considered to be federal public servants, and in addition to appointing the other members of the duchy-level administrations, these executives should be responsible for appointing the heads and lieutenant heads of the counties, and these county-level executives should naturally be considered duchy-level public servants and appoint the other members of the county-level administrations. Their heads should have the same disciplinary powers as the heads of class three duchies, and the heads of their counties should be able to subject the county-level public servants of their counties to equivalent disciplinary measures. Their baronies should function in a similar way as the baronies of class one and class two duchies.
Class five duchies should have no elections, their interduchy borders should be very heavily guarded, and traveling within them should be very controlled. Their heads should, of course, be appointed by the monarch and considered federal public servants, and their duchy-level administrations and the heads of their counties should be appointed by their heads. The appointed heads of their counties should naturally be considered to be duchy-level public servants and appoint the other members of the county-level administrations and the heads of their baronies, and the heads of their baronies should be considered to be county-level public servants and appoint the barony-level administrations. Their heads should, of course, have the same disciplinary powers as the heads of class three and class four duchies, and the heads of their counties and baronies should naturally have equivalent disciplinary powers within their counties and baronies, respectively.

States should be able to join the federation if the proposals for how they would be incorporated into the federation are approved by both chambers of the parliament. Proposals for incorporating more than one state should not be allowed, and the proposals should naturally be voted on one at a time. Approving such proposals should normally require two-thirds majorities, but approving proposals opposed by the monarch should require four-fifths majorities. If the incorporation of a state into the federation would result in the creation of a class one duchy, a number of class one duchies, at least one class one special intrarealm polity, a class one separate island territory, or multiple class one separate island territories, the incorporation proposal should also require the approval of a two-thirds majority of the federal electorate as the last step.
The parliament should normally be able to change the classifications of non-class one duchies, non-class one special intrarealm polities, and non-class one separate island territories permanently with two-thirds majorities, but if the monarch opposes such a change, it should require four-fifths majorities. It should not be possible for the parliament to change a permanent classification by more than one class at once, and each change should be voted on separately. Changing the classification of a duchy, a special intrarealm polity, or a separate island territory to class one should also require the approval of a two-thirds majority of the federal electorate. The parliament should be able to expel class five duchies, equivalent special intrarealm polities, and equivalent separate island territories from the federation in the same way as it should be able to change the permanent classifications of duchies, special intrarealm polities, and separate island territories.
The parliament should also be able to change the classifications of non-class one duchies, special intrarealm polities, and separate island territories temporarily by one for a year at a time up to five consecutive years with simple majorities, but if the monarch is opposed to a temporary change of classification or an extension of such a change, it should require two-thirds majorities. If a change of classification is not made permanent nor extended, the parliament should not be able to change it temporarily for as many years as the classification was consecutively different from the permanent classification.
The classifications of class one duchies, class one special intrarealm polities, and class one separate island territories should be unchangeable.
Duchies and special intrarealm polities should be allowed to merge with other duchies and special intrarealm polities of the same classes, and they should also be able to transfer territory to other duchies and special intrarealm polities, but such mergers and transfers should require approvals from both chambers of the parliament with two-thirds majorities.
Duchies should also be able to divide into two or more duchies or special intrarealm polities of the same class, and special intrarealm polities should be able to divide into two or more special intrarealm polities of the same class, and a change of this kind should require the approval of both chambers of the parliament with simple majorities.
Duchies and special intrarealm polities should be able to become independent of the federation if two thirds of both chambers of the parliament vote in favour of granting the intrarealm polity in question independence and the monarch assents to granting it independence.

The armed forces should be mostly reservist based, but there should be no conscription: the system should be based on people being offered service contracts with good enough terms for there to be sufficient amounts of people signing up for the initial periods of service and the associated reservist commitments. It seems that a system of this kind would work even in wartime if a sufficiently large proportion of the population eligible for service thinks that the state is worth fighting for.

There should be so much military education capacity that every person who is eligible for military service and willing to serve is able to enter service. People who have served honourably should get bonuses when they are transferred to the reserve and when they are discharged from military service, and the sizes of the bonuses should depend on their performance and conduct while in service in addition to their rank. Reservists should, of course, get paid for attending refresher courses and supplementary training, but how much they get paid for doing so should be strongly dependent on how fit they are, and the maximum payments should be so substantial that at least the primary reserve would stay on average in very good or even excellent physical condition.

The sex of a person should not be taken into consideration when determining what duties they should be allowed to serve in. The standardized tests for the measurement of servicemembers’ and potential servicemembers’ physical fitness should be designed to give a reasonably accurate idea of how the people being tested can perform physically when fully equipped, and thus they should wear well-designed and approximately equally heavy weight vests during the tests. In addition, it would seem that grooming standards should be equally rational and thus the same for every servicemember, with the exception of reservists who haven’t been called into full time service, of course.

The monarch should normally be the supreme commander of the armed forces, and if the throne is occupied by a regent, the regent should be the supreme commander. There should be realm-, duchy-, county-, and barony-level forces, and the intrarealm polities’ forces should be as reservist based as reasonably possible and primarily organized and equipped for defence. Both the supreme commander and the parliament should have the right to bring intrarealm polities’ forces under federal command temporarily, and the expenses of intrarealm polities’ forces under federal command should naturally be paid for by the federal government. The system should work in a similar fashion within the duchies and the counties.
The vast majority of the professional servicemembers of the combined land and aerospace forces of the realm should be members of the intrarealm polities’ forces.
The realm-level forces should be mostly composed of full-time professionals and very capable of offensive operations and expeditionary warfare.
The bulk of the realm-level/federal forces should be seamlessly and thoroughly integrated combined arms marines, and their landing craft should belong to the marine corps rather than the navy. The intrarealm polities too could, of course, have amphibious forces.
The federal navy should be a blue-water navy, and the intrarealm polities’ navies should be green- and/or brown-water navies. The aerospace arm of the federal navy should be primarily an air-superiority force, and it should carry out strike missions only as necessary.
All members of the armed forces should naturally be subject to federal military law, and it should be the only military law in the realm.

All servicemembers should receive a substantial amount of education about civics and philosophy and arguably also be taught how to think and act essentially like champions of freedom (compare to, e.g. German Freiheitskämpfer, ”freedom fighters”) rather than, for example, ”mere soldiers” more or less just going through the motions, but this should naturally be done in a very matter-of-fact, absolutely no-nonsense way.
All servicemembers should give secular pledges of fidelity, i.e. all of them should give affirmations. Their highest official duty should be the protection of the constitutional order, and their affirmations should, of course, reflect this very clearly, and thus they should pledge that they will support and defend the constitution and serve the realm and be faithful to both, and the affirmations should never include pledges of fidelity to anything else.

It would seem that there is a clear need for the state to be able to act very decisively in difficult times, and therefore it seems sufficiently reasonable for both the parliament and the electorate to have the right to grant the monarch the right to rule by decree for a year at a time. The decrees of the monarch should, of course, not be able to override the constitution in any way, but they should naturally override all provisions of normal statutes they are in conflict with, except those concerning elections, and they should have the force of law only for as long as the monarch has the right to rule by decree plus one hundred days.
If there have been, for example, three consecutive years during which the monarch has not had the right to rule by decree, the count of how many times the parliament has granted said right should automatically reset. The parliament should be able to grant the right to rule by decree independently perhaps three times without having to wait for a reset of the count, consecutively or non-consecutively. If the electorate grants the right to rule by decree, the count should reset. If the parliament has granted the right to rule by decree the maximum amount of times it can do so without waiting for a reset of the count, it should be able to call a referendum on whether the right to rule by decree should granted again. It should be possible to grant the right to rule by decree only to the individual who is the monarch, and it should naturally be automatically revoked if the monarch changes.
If the parliament grants the right to rule by decree, the electorate should be able to call a monarchical election right away.

Both chambers of the parliament, the cabinet, the monarch, and regents should be able to declare a state of emergency, and a state of emergency should normally last for a year if the parliament does not extend it. Both chambers of the parliament, the cabinet, the monarch, and regents should naturally be able to also decide that the state of emergency ends at a specified time. During a state of emergency, the cabinet should be able to issue executive orders specifying which provisions of the emergency powers act should be applied and how, and it should not be legal to apply provisions of the act the application of which is not necessary to deal with the situation appropriately. These orders should stay in force for a maximum of a hundred days if at least one chamber of the parliament votes against keeping the order in force for a longer time, and if the state of emergency ends, the order should automatically cease being in force. If the parliament decides to extend the time for which the order stays in force, the duration of the state of emergency should be automatically extended to match, and it should be possible to extend the time for which the order stays in force only by up to a year from the day of such an extension. The parliament should also be able to decide to keep the order in force only partially.
The parliament, the monarch and regents should also be able to declare martial law in the whole realm or a part of the realm, and if martial law is declared, the realm should also automatically enter a state of emergency, and it should naturally not be possible to end a state of emergency if martial law is in force. If martial law is in force, the monarch and regents should be able to issue orders specifying which provisions of the martial law act should be applied and how, and it should not be legal to authorize applying provisions of the martial law act the application of which is not necessary to deal with the situation at hand. Martial law should stay in force for a maximum of a hundred days if at least one chamber of the parliament votes against keeping it in force for a longer time, and the parliament, the monarch, and regents should, of course, be able to decide that martial law will cease being in force at a specific time, and the parliament should be able to extend the time for which martial law remains in force only by up to a year from the day of such an extension. If martial law ceases to be in force, the orders concerning the application of the provisions of the martial law act should naturally automatically cease being in force, and the parliament should also be able to decide to keep such orders in force only partially.
If the parliament or a chamber thereof is unable to vote on whether to keep the realm in a state of emergency within a hundred days of the state of emergency being declared, the realm should remain in a state of emergency until the state of emergency is ended by a chamber of the parliament, the cabinet, the monarch, or a regent if martial law is not in force, of course, and if the parliament or a chamber of the parliament is unable to vote on an order concerning the use of emergency powers within a hundred days of the issuance of the order, the order should remain in force until a chamber of the parliament votes against keeping it in force. If the parliament or a chamber thereof is unable to vote or whether to keep martial law in force within a hundred days of the declaration of martial law, martial law should remain in force until the parliament, the monarch, or a regent decides that martial law will cease being in force at a specific time.
If the monarch or a regent declares a state of emergency or issues an order declaring martial law, both chambers of the parliament and the electorate should be able to call a monarchical election immediately.
Changing the emergency powers act and the martial law act should require two successive lower chambers of the parliament and the upper chamber of the parliament voting in favour of the proposed changes with two-thirds majorities and the approval of the monarch, in that order.

The chambers of the parliament should be able to postpone normally scheduled elections to them only by up to a year at a time, and such postponements should also be subject to approval by the monarch. The monarch should have the right to call early parliamentary elections and also the right to dissolve the parliament or just a single chamber thereof. If the parliament or a chamber of the parliament is dissolved, elections to the parliament or the dissolved chamber should be held within one hundred days of the dissolution. The outgoing cabinet should become a caretaker cabinet by default if the parliament (or the lower chamber) has been dissolved, but the monarch should also have the right to appoint a caretaker cabinet composed of independents.
The electorate should be able to call a monarchical election immediately if the monarch calls an early parliamentary election or dissolves the parliament or a chamber thereof, and the monarch should not be able to dissolve a chamber of the parliament if less than a year has passed since its most recent dissolution. The rights of the monarch to call early parliamentary elections and dissolve the parliament and the chambers of the parliament should be automatically suspended if a monarchical election has been called and remain suspended until the election results have been verified, or until the winner of the election has been coronated if the incumbent loses the election.

It seems reasonable to call a state of this kind a freerealm, and calques (loan translations) of this term would also seem to convey the general idea fairly well. The second part of the calque of freerealm into German is, of course, somewhat problematic when it is used alone or as the leading word in compounds, at least for now, due to some of the things fairly commonly associated with it, but on the other hand as it simply means “realm”/”state”/”empire”, it has naturally also been used for very long times both in compounds to refer to, for example, France, Austria, and the UK and in some cases also as a separate word following a proper noun, like when referring to, e.g. ancient Rome. Avoiding its use in the official name of the Germans’ own state in German in perpetuity would thus seem a little strange, and obviously especially so if said state is a federation the population of which is composed of multiple European peoples including other major ones.
Calques of freerealm into some European languages are, for example, royaume libre (French), vrijrijk (Netherlandic), reino libre (Castilian), reino livre (Portuguese), reame libero (Italian), saorríocht (Irish), fririge (Danish), fririke (Norwegian and Swedish), fríríki (Icelandic), Fräiräich (Luxembourgish), and naturally Freireich. In my native Finnish the corresponding term is vapaavaltakunta, and the Estonian equivalent is vabariik, which also means “republic”.

There is, of course, also the question of the title of the monarch. It would seem to make sense to derive suitable terms from words derived from the reconstructed proto-Indo-European root of most of the aforementioned terms for realm: the root in question is *h₃rḗǵ- (“to straighten”, “to right oneself”, “right”, “just”), and the words right, rectify, direct, correct, Richter (“a judge”), Recht (“a right”, “a privilege”, “the law”, “a title”, “a claim”), gerecht (“just”, “fair”), Gericht (“a court of law”, “a judgement”), regulate, rule, regent, regal, rēx, rēgīna, royal, reign, rā́jan (“a king”, “a sovereign”, “a monarch”, “a prince”), rā́jñī (“a queen”, “a princess”, “a wife of a monarch”), and rājyá (“a kingdom”, “a country”, “a realm”, “royalty”, “kingship”, “sovereignty”, “empire”, “kingly”, “princely”, “royal”), for example, are also derived from this root.
The reconstructed proto-Indo-European terms for male and female monarchs are *h₃rḗǵs and *h₃rḗǵnih₂, and the reconstructed native proto-Germanic derivatives of the former are *rekô and *rekaz, which were displaced by *rīks, which is a borrowing from proto-Celtic. The reconstructed proto-Celtic term for a male monarch is *rīxs, and the feminine equivalent is *rīganī, and the descendants of these also include, for example, Cymric/West Brittonic/Welsh rhi and rhiain (“king” and “maiden”), Irish and ríon (“king” and “queen”), Manx ree and rein (“king” and “queen”), and Scottish Gaelic rìgh and rìghinn (“king” and “queen”).
English terms for the monarchs of a freerealm derived from *rīxs and *rīganī could perhaps be rix (/ɹɪks/) and rigan (/‘ɹɪɡən/, compare to Wigan, /ˈwɪɡən/); using a non-gender-specific term is, of course, also a possibility. These terms should naturally simply mean “ruler” in the sense of something along the lines of “state manager”, which is quite well in line with their etymologies, and “state manager” is also a fairly adequate term for what kind of a person the monarch would in my opinion ideally be: a level-headed individual at the helm who would typically stay relatively detached from and thus most likely be less subject to the “wearing” effects of day-to-day politics, but who would also be able to take a much more hands-on approach when appropriate. Some people might, of course, use traditional monarchical titles in reference to the monarchs anyway, and such titles could naturally be made co-official, but even if they are co-official, the monarchs should be able to decide whether they want traditional titles to be used in official contexts in reference to them or not.

For comparison to the terms for “state manager”, imperātor and imperātrīx and thus also, for example, emperor and empress and empereur and impératrice are derivedfrom the word imperō, which means “I command, I give orders to, I rule, I govern, I demand, I impose”, and the most accurate translations of the aforementioned agent nouns into German would thus seem to be Gebieter and Gebieterin; terms of this kind could perhaps be used to refer to monarchs who have been granted the right to rule by decree for as long as they have said right.
On a related note, the use of terms for rulers and states derived from Caesar seems rather silly, except in historical contexts, of course, and/or if they are used derisively, and letting the ghosts of Gaius Julius Caesar and the Roman Empire sleep more soundly in a way would seem to be quite appropriate, considering that Caesar was rather clearly relatively unwise, i.e. benighted and that the Empire too was obviously quite far from ideal.
It would seem to be a good idea to seek to rise above all kinds of distorted views of the past, or maybe rather to strive to see things of the past for what they actually were, and naturally also to use the most sensible terms that we can come up with.

While understanding the past is obviously of profound importance, and being firmly rooted in it in this sense is thus quite clearly rather rational, a fairly highly future-oriented approach to policymaking seems eminently reasonable: in a state of this freerealm kind, the head of state would usually be able to delegate handling the more day-to-day affairs of the state to the head of government and the cabinet and thus to act primarily as a strategic leader, and they would ideally, of course, also be a calm, rational person with a steadying firm hand.

A suggestion for a solution to the Palestinian issue

Establishing a viable Palestinian state would seem to be at least technically feasible. It is, of course, fairly apparent that doing so would be rather challenging, particularly politically, of course, and given the complexity of the political process aspect of the issue, for now it seems best to focus mostly on what it would take to create the foundations of a viable Palestinian state rather than on how exactly to make it happen politically, and it would also seem reasonable to avoid going deep into the details concerning the solution itself in this post.

The history of the region is obviously fairly complex, and as such it would seem sensible to also not discuss it any more than absolutely necessary in this context in order to avoid going off the main topic.

The territory of the new Palestinian state should be contiguous. The region in question should be divided roughly into two halves, and it seems like an at least somewhat sensible compromise to make the border between them a reasonable line of some kind running from the Mediterranean to the Dead Sea north of Ashdod and Kiryat Gat and south of Jerusalem, all things considered, with the southern half naturally becoming the territory of the new Palestinian state.
The Palestinian state should, of course, also have a robust constitution, and the fledgling state should naturally be closely supervised and guided, preferably by a European body of some kind.
The state should naturally also have a reasonable security policy and a sound economic system with a clear focus on positive liberty. Creating economic opportunities for the Palestinians is, of course, critically important from a security point of view too, since they must have a fairly positive outlook in order for the extremism among them to slowly fade away.
Establishing an education system capable of providing high-quality education is obviously a priority as well.
The tax system should, of course, be fairly simple and relatively easily enforceable, and the euro could perhaps be used as an interim currency.
There naturally should also be a decent social security system without incentive traps, and healthcare charges should be fairly small.

Energy security is, of course, very important as well, and it seems that a combination of at least solar power, pumped storage, and hydrogen storage (naturally in tandem with fuel cells) seems like a feasible basis for a fairly dependable electricity sector. Local related manufacturing should naturally be fostered and the domestic energy market should become competitive as soon as possible in order to drive electricity costs down fairly quickly.
An ample supply of electricity would, of course, also allow for a dependable supply of desalinated water, which would naturally also help with food security.

The new Palestinian state should naturally receive a substantial amount of aid in order to help set it up, but the proportion of financial aid of all of the aid should be as small as possible in order to avoid fostering corruption and long-term financial dependence as well as reasonably possible, and the vast majority of the aid should thus be provided mostly as goods and services, with a particular focus on quality education, of course.
The state should also be given military assistance by an at least mostly European force. Training police and military personnel should naturally be a high priority too.
Establishing full sovereignty over all of the de jure territory of the new state should be left to be the responsibility of the new local armed forces, and the military assistance should become peacekeeping as soon as reasonably possible.

This kind of a solution would obviously have a very significant economic impact on the Jews of the region, but this would seem like a justifiable compromise, as it seems rather reasonable to see the Jews as owing the Palestinians a lot.
The Jewish state could perhaps use its power of expropriation to purchase land and buildings within the territory to be handed over to the Palestinians, and it could then pass the property to an international holding body overseen by the states supervising the new Palestinian state, and if this is done, the property should then be passed to Palestinian ownership as soon as reasonably possible: avoiding corruption in the process as much as possible is obviously very important.
The Jews’ legitimate security concerns regarding all of this should, of course, be acknowledged as such, but it seems obvious that an arrangement like this would also make some security work considerably simpler for them. Both the new Palestinian state and the Jewish state should naturally have to formally recognize each other as legitimate and renounce all claims to each others’ territory for good in a treaty. The treaty should, of course, also specify the total amount of reparations to be paid by the Jews and make it clear that the Jews do not owe Palestinians any per se reparations in excess of what is specified in the treaty.

Economic and social development in Palestine and increased trade between Jews and Palestinians should help considerably in maintaining and reinforcing peace between the two peoples, and it seems plausible that the vast majorities of the peoples of both countries might come to fully accept the new status quo in a generation or two and that the arrangement would prove to be mutually beneficial for them in the long term.

European unity and how it might be possible to build a fairly resilient European federation

I am firmly convinced that if we Europeans form a federation, at some point the result could be the most advanced and powerful civilization in history. We obviously have our differences, but if we develop our ability to utilize our collective cultural richness as a resource, it would increasingly foster greater understanding and innovation. It seems equally obvious that we could fairly dependably build on what we have in common and that we might be able to utilize the strength of facts to overcome the difficulties created by our differences.

It would appear to be fairly clear that we need to be able to work together much more efficiently if we don’t want to be to a very significant degree subject to the influence of people who don’t exactly consider our well-being the highest of priorities. Greater unity would thus seem to be exactly what we need going forward, and given how much we have in common already, it might be surprisingly readily achievable, provided that we focus primarily on what we have in common and all of the other things that truly matter most. To me it seems rather clear that there is so much more beyond a veil of fear and confusion: a new, more concerted kind of Europe awaiting its birth. Building a properly functioning European federation would, of course, be a fairly challenging endeavour, but it would seem to be possible with the right kind of approach.

Since it would appear that a system of government built on strong distrust is relatively likely to be well-functioning and prosocial, it seems most appropriate to seek to build the foundations of a European federation with the same principle in mind, or in other words, to build the whole system around checks and balances that are as strong as reasonably possible without being excessively burdensome. Establishing this kind of a system that has a very clear emphasis on the safeguarding of the rights and liberties of the people and that operates in a relatively sensible fashion is in my opinion most likely the only way in which a European federation can be built, since it would seem that any people with its own sovereign state is rather unlikely to relinquish its national sovereignty if they perceive that there is a substantial chance that such a decision would make their prospects worse, and especially so if they think that it is possible that they might end up being oppressed as a result of such a change, and obviously extremely so if it seems even a little likely that the possible oppression would be totalitarian in nature.

Accomplishing the establishment of a European federation with a top-down approach, i.e. turning the European Union into a federation seems rather implausible, since entering into an unproven system of such nature would seem to be intolerably risky for the vast majority of the people involved. Therefore it would appear to be fairly clear that the only way in which at least most of Europe can reasonably be expected to become a federation without the use of military force is with a bottom-up approach, i.e. via a state (or maybe up to a few states) becoming a federation with a constitution with the necessary checks and balances and then fairly conclusively proving that the system actually works properly and that joining the federation is the superior alternative to keeping national sovereignty and then enlarging it piece by piece at a pace that allows the federal government to function properly without exception. Ideally the states or parts thereof joining the federation should border it or be readily accessible by sea through domestic and international waters, but exceptions could obviously be made in situations that demand it.

Prior to settling on a final draft of the federal constitution, substantial effort should, of course, be put into studying what solutions have been successful in other federations and naturally also what they have failed at, with a particular focus on studying the oldest federation in existence: the United States of America is obviously a deeply flawed country, but it is still quite clearly worthy of emulation in many ways, and I am reasonably confident that it is possible for us to create a superb federation in Europe if we put sufficient effort into the process of crafting the constitution and legislation in general and take a very deliberately eclectic approach to both.

If the state is genuinely highly prosocial, it seems likely that its citizens would be on average fairly supportive of it and that a very considerable proportion of them might be quite motivated to fight for it as well.

Economic policy suggestions

From a prosocial perspective, it seems eminently reasonable to seek to foster a healthier economy in the society in question, and one way to do this would, of course, be to increase the average efficiency of the economic actors in that society, and given that worker co-operatives are apparently on average not only the most efficient corporations but also the most resilient, keeping the aforementioned perspective it would seem particularly rational to enact policies that would increase such co-operatives’ proportion of the economy. From the same point of view it seems very sensible to also make the establishment of not only innovative limited companies but limited companies in general as uncomplicated as reasonably possible and to give inventive employees healthier incentives.

It seems that a substantial increase in the proportion of worker co-operatives could be achieved by establishing a number of state funding agencies that would finance especially the founding stages of worker co-operatives bound by a certain legally fixed set of rules. Co-operatives like this could be called employees’ corporations, for example, and I’ll use this term for this type of co-operative at least for now.
The agencies should also fund conversions of existing businesses into employees’ corporations through buyouts. They should fund innovative limited companies as well, especially in the founding stages, since a limited company seems quite likely to be the most suitable form of corporation for a primarily innovator-driven business. They should, of course, be able to fund less innovative limited companies too. They should also be allowed to fund more conventional transfers of limited company ownership. It should, of course, be possible to found employees’ corporations with private funding as well.

The agencies should be able to have both solo investors and investment teams, and the investors and the members of the investment teams should naturally have a legally mandated non-disclosure duty, and provided that the state has a fairly solid reputation for consistently enforcing the rule of law, this would obviously make it possible for people to simply get in touch with investors and investment teams and discuss their business plans without having to worry too much about their ideas getting stolen.
Even if the state has a good reputation, there should probably also be a standing recommendation for people to make sufficient records of their communication with the investors and the investment teams, just in case.

The investors and the members of the investment teams should have relatively modest base salaries, but each solo investor and investment team should naturally also get a share of the net profits they generate for the agencies. They should also get automatically dismissed if their ”accounts” are in the negative for too long, and the amounts they are in the negative and the potentials of their investments should be taken into consideration when determining the length of time that qualifies as too long, but there should be an algorithm that would take a general economic downturn into consideration when their performance would be automatically evaluated so that the dismissal of sufficiently competent people could be avoided. Dismissed investors should, however, get their share of the net profits their investments might ultimately end up generating; if another investor or investment team working for the agency or some other agency takes over a case by investing more into the corporation in question, how much each investor and investment team gets paid should be proportional to the amount they have invested in the corporation relative to the total amount invested in that corporation via their agency or agencies.

The funding agencies should have to be self-sustaining, and therefore if the agency-funded corporations that have not reached their investment targets have surplus, they should have to pay the agencies if demanded to do so by those who invested in them until they reach their return-on-investment targets, after which they would be independent. The agencies should have ownership of the corporations that have not become independent of them in order for the investors and investment teams to have the ability to recoup some of the potential losses, but besides being able to dictate how much of the possible net surplus of the corporations would be paid to the agencies and when, the investors and the investment teams should have no control over the corporations.
Corporations that have not become independent from the agencies could be called bound corporations, for example, and bound employees’ corporations would, of course, essentially be agency owned and employee controlled limited companies instead of worker co-operatives.
Limited companies still in agency ownership should, of course, have designated potential owners who would control the companies as if they were the owners, except regarding the payments to the agencies, obviously.
The return-on-investment target percentage should be set by law to a level that would ensure that sufficiently well-functioning agencies can make enough profit to not only sustain themselves but also grow without taking on debt.
Agencies that fail to sustain themselves should simply be automatically abolished.
Because the corporations would become independent upon reaching their return-on-investment targets, the investors would, of course, have a fairly strong incentive to remain active.
The agencies should be legal persons, and they should operate much like employees’ corporations.

The head of state, the head of government, the parliament, and the ministry that would be responsible for most of the supervision of the funding agencies should be able to order funding agencies to be established. Funding agencies should be establishable also by the administrative units of the state. The armed forces, the branches thereof, and the ministry of military affairs should also be permitted to establish funding agencies and naturally also to supervise funding agencies they have established, but funding agencies established by them should be allowed to invest only in services supporting the functions of the armed forces and in the production of military equipment.
The initial capital of the agencies should arguably be loans from the state and the administrative units, and they should naturally be able to lend the agencies more too. The agencies should be able to take on debt from the private sector as well.

There should be a special type of corporation to make it easy to distinguish the employees’ corporations from other kinds of worker co-operatives, and there could also be two subtypes of it to allow people to easily tell bound and independent ones apart. If these types of corporations are called employees’ corporations also legally, they could obviously be abbreviated as Bec/bec and Ec/ec.
The core ruleset of the employees’ corporations should be legally mandated so that all of them would be on fairly equal footing in terms of rules, and it seems that a core ruleset with the following rules would enable the corporations to function fairly well:
1. Every employee has one vote.
2. The board is elected by the employees, and all employees are eligible to become candidates for board membership.
3. A binding employees’ vote (on should a new board election be held or should a specific employee be removed from a position or dismissed altogether, for example) will be had if at least 10 % of the employees demand one, provided that the number of employees making the demand is at least two.
4. An advisory employees’ vote will be had if at least 5 % of the employees demand one.
5. Every employee has the right to bring up to two (or maybe three) outsiders to observe the voting and the counting of votes (there should also be a number of experts in the overseeing ministry and maybe in the ministry of justice as well who could be invited to observe the proceedings).
6. Company funds may not be used for campaigning to influence internal elections nor employee votes.
7. The share of the dividend each employee gets is equal to their share of the sum total of all salaries and bonuses paid by the company during the preceding full fiscal year.
8. Whether to pay dividend and how much is decided by direct employee vote, but bound employees’ corporations are obligated to pay the funding agencies before paying dividend if demanded to do so, of course.
9. Independent employees’ corporations can be converted to any other type of corporation (with some fixed minimum delay) if at least two thirds of the employees are in favour of doing so, and the form of corporation and other details can be decided either at the same time or with a separate vote.
Violating these rules should naturally be criminal.

Employees’ corporations would obviously operate on the market under normal market regulations, but given that they would not only be relatively efficient and resilient but probably also favoured to some degree by the general public over other types of corporations, they might become very significant on the market, perhaps even fairly quickly, and a country establishing a system like this might experience an at least somewhat prolonged period of rapid economic development, and it would, of course, fairly likely also gain a substantial or even a relatively decisive competitive edge over otherwise comparable countries without equivalent or similar systems.
If there is a perceived need to protect the system and thus also economic and social stability from fluctuating political trends, the right of the people to have a system of this nature could obviously be enshrined in the constitution as well.

A law regarding employee inventions more or less along the lines of the following would seem likely to have some positive effects:
Employees should have the rights to all inventions they make on the job as a result of their possible research and development duties, but they should be obligated to licence them semi-exclusively to the employer they were working for when they made the invention. Semi-exclusivity would mean that they would not be allowed to licence the intellectual property in question to any other party without an agreement with the employer, with the exception of another employer for which they work. They should, of course, be allowed to sell the rights to their inventions by default, but it should naturally be possible for them to enter into contracts which stipulate that they agree to not do so for defined periods of time, and they should also be allowed to agree to not exploit the inventions in question for as long as the patents in question are in force or for shorter periods of time so that the employers for which the inventors involved made their inventions would have better chances to profit from their investments into the research and development projects leading to the inventions in question. People should, of course, also be allowed to enter into employment contracts which stipulate that the inventions they make during their employment are automatically licenced to their employer if the licencing terms agreed upon in the employment contract are met. The inventors should only be allowed to sell the rights to their inventions after they have signed the obligatory licence agreements or after the patents have been granted if a licence agreement regarding the invention is not yet in force, and if an inventor or a group of inventors sells the rights to their invention and a licence agreement is in force, the licence agreement should naturally bind the new owner of the rights to the invention. The new owner should also not be allowed to licence said intellectual property to any other party except the employer for which the inventor(s) made the invention without a written agreement with the employer in question, and they should, of course, be obligated to licence the invention to the employer for which the inventor(s) made the invention in question if a licence agreement is not in force when the rights to the invention is transferred to the new owner. If the employers the inventors were working for when they made their inventions agree that the right to use the inventions can be licenced to others, the proceeds from such licencing should be shared equally between the owners of the rights to the inventions and the employers for which they made the inventions.

There shouldn’t be a legally defined minimum royalty percentage for obligatory licences, but there should be a legal requirement for the compensation for the obligatory licences to be at least adequate relative to the benefits provided by the patents in question, and if an agreement regarding the terms of an obligatory licence has not been reached within, for example, 100 days after a patent application has been filed, it should be possible for the parties involved to take the matter to a competent court. The royalties should be calculated by multiplying the base prices before taxes with the royalty rates.
It seems likely that a signing bonus equal to some fairly modest percentage of a reasonably conservative estimate of the value of the invention would be the norm in licencing agreements, since it would seem to make a lot of sense for companies to pay such bonuses without much encouragement.

In cases in which an invention has multiple inventors, the inventors should share the royalties equally if they haven’t made a contract regarding their shares of the rights to the invention. If a product utilizes a number of inventions covered by the law regarding employee inventions, the royalties paid could be calculated as follows, for example: the total royalty percentage paid to the owners of the patents covering the employee inventions could be equal to that of the invention with the highest percentage plus the others added up and divided by ten (or maybe five), and the royalties would be shared between the holders of the patents according to the royalty percentage(s) of their patent(s) divided by all of the royalty percentages added up, for example, i.e. if a product utilized 3 patents with royalty rates of 7 %, 8 %, and 11 %, the owner of the patent with the 7 % royalty rate would get 7 / 26 of the royalties, the total rate of which would be 12,5 % (or 14 %).
It seems that this way the market prices of products utilizing even a relatively large number of inventions licenced from inventive employees would also stay at a fairly reasonable level, and all of the owners of the applied patents would get rewarded more or less properly.

It seems quite likely that corporations primarily driven by a single key person or a small group of key people would continue to be limited companies to a significant degree and probably even for the most part in cases in which the key people are also the owners. Employees’ corporations would seem fairly likely to be very key person driven as well, as they might be able to retain innovators and other key people quite consistently, given that they too would obviously have quite strong incentives to pay key personnel adequately, and especially considering that employees’ corporations would probably be relatively likely to have healthy workplace cultures.

A lot of key-person-driven corporations would obviously rather likely keep getting founded as privately funded limited companies as well. There should arguably also be a form of limited company the establishment and operation of which would not require the involvement of more than one person, and if these are an option, it should, of course, also be possible to establish corporations of this kind through funding agencies as bound corporations.
Business arrangements involving inventive corporations and individuals outsourcing manufacturing and/or licencing a patent or patents to an employees’ corporation or multiple would probably be quite common in an economy utilizing this kind of a system, since they would most likely be the most efficient options more often than not and due to greater average efficiency probably also more common than similar arrangements in comparable economies in which employees have less healthy incentives on average.

In the lead-up to and following the establishment of a system like this, private investment in the economy would, of course, be less attractive, and thus the transition period might be somewhat difficult, but it seems that the negative impact might be fairly moderate, i.e. manageable if the funding agencies are provided with ample funds and especially if the system is established at a time when private investment in the economy is already at a relatively low level.

All things considered, the resulting system would seem to be one in which inventive employees would have fairly healthy incentives, employees in general would be relatively difficult to abuse, starting and buying businesses would be relatively easy, corporations would have less superfluous management on average, employees would be on average more productive and also happier and thus probably healthier too, and it seems that the economy in general would quite likely work significantly better after the transition period, and thus it would seem that the unemployment and underemployment rates would also most likely be lower than before it. In addition, it seems that the immigration of many kinds of professionals and especially of the innovative kind might increase quite considerably, provided that the other qualities of the society in question don’t make it somehow repulsive, obviously.

A bit about weapon rights and some related matters

Are you in favour of relatively unlimited individual weapon rights? If you are not, you might want to reconsider: I like to think that my reasoning behind this claim is quite convincing.
Before moving on to the aforementioned reasoning, I would like to make it clear that among other things, I design firearms and other kinds of weapons, and why I do so should become fairly obvious if you read the rest of this entry. I am, of course, arguably at least somewhat biased concerning these matters, but it doesn’t seem very rational to simply assume that I am so biased that my arguments about them are somehow deeply flawed or even completely invalid.

It seems to me that power is not intrinsically corruptive, but also that the corrupt tend to seek power and that only the absolutely corrupt seek absolute power, and from this viewpoint, it would seem to be quite sensible for people to seek to safeguard their rights and liberties as well as reasonably possible. Those who are fundamentally opposed to liberty will, of course, work against such safeguarding efforts in a rather consistent, arguably even compulsive manner. It is obviously a priority for such people to seek to deprive the people whom they seek to repress of weapons that can be used as effective means of resistance against repression, especially of the kinds of weapons that are particularly suitable for military and paramilitary uses, of course, and thus it seems that it should be made clear that rifles in this latter category of weapons are used only in relatively small proportions of criminal homicides and other violent crimes involving firearms committed in the United States of America, and that the vast majority of them are, in fact, also at least good and relatively often even excellent for defensive and sporting uses.

To me it seems quite obvious that a state is an entity separate from a people, ideally much like a corporation is from its owners, and that one at least should be just a tool, i.e. a means to an end rather than a self-justifying end in itself, and it would seem to be approximately equally obvious that a state will act only as prosocially as it has to, and it is, of course, rather difficult for a people to coerce a state if they are not suitably equipped to do so.
It would appear to be quite sensible to want to live in a society in which the people don’t have to essentially just hope that the state and obviously law enforcement and the armed forces in particular won’t turn against them at some point due to, for example, systematic extremist infiltration, i.e. to want to have a society in which the people have an overwhelmingly strong ability to keep state power in check instead of a society that is essentially based on wishful thinking. Some people, however, seem to be so indoctrinated and/or enthralled by their fantasies of in some ways relatively unrestricted power, greater wealth, higher social status, and/or ”glory” that they rather conveniently ignore the quite distinct possibility that a society in which at least just about everyone can in practice be coerced to serve it indefinitely is not necessarily a great idea.

The abolition of liberty would seem to be a real threat at least for now, even if it seems like a fairly remote one at the moment. Things can, however, change quite rapidly, as is well known, and it seems that it should be kept in mind that the replacement of liberty with abject repression might happen as a consequence of the relative foolishness of only a single generation. It would thus seem quite reasonable for a people to invest amply in education.
It seems that combining an education system in which a very considerable proportion of the eligible population gets at least half a year or so of military education (including civics classes) with constitutionally guaranteed weapon rights (with some reasonable limitations, of course) would also help to perpetuate liberty: it is obviously relatively difficult to successfully limit the rights and liberties of a people arbitrarily and/or to carry out a coup d’état or a violent revolution successfully if a large proportion of the population in question is opposed to such actions, genuinely capable of well-organized paramilitary and/or military operations against their domestic enemies, and determined to crush them. A well-armed civilian population is, of course, also an extra deterrent against invasion.

From the viewpoint of prioritizing the safeguarding of liberty, a registry of privately owned weapons seems like an eminently bad idea, even though such a registry can, of course, be helpful when used for legitimate purposes, since such a registry can obviously also be used to, for example, facilitate mass confiscation of weapons and/or the creation of a database of people who are, on average, relatively likely to engage in armed resistance against a repressive state and/or to support such resistance. Weapon registry data is, of course, also very attractive to a state or states planning to invade the country in question. Burglars, too, might want to acquire weapon registry data so that they would know which dwellings are relatively safe to burgle even when the inhabitants are present and which dwellings to burgle when the inhabitants are not present if they want to steal weapons. Taking into account all of the ways such a registry can be abused, it seems that the existence of one is arguably a rather considerable threat to the people living under the jurisdiction of a state with one.
Law enforcement work is obviously more inconvenient without the aid of such a registry than with such aid, but at least in this context it doesn’t seem very reasonable to prioritize what is convenient for law enforcement when crafting potentially extremely significant legislation. Law enforcement officers who have to cope with the inconvenience of not having such a registry at their disposal should, of course, be trained and paid relatively well.
In my opinion, there should, however, be a non-logging, well-maintained, robust, easy-to-use system for making instant background checks in order to help prevent and reduce the possession of weapons subject to legal restrictions by people who are not legally allowed to possess them, and the use of a system like this arguably shouldn’t require any special qualifications so that it would fulfil its purpose as well as possible.

States obviously tend to be relatively very significant concentrations of power, and thus it would seem to be quite sensible to maintain a reasonable degree of suspicion towards them.

The legacy of the Franks

History has been shaped to a relatively significant degree by the Franks and the continuums that they started. But who were these people, where did they come from, and what became of them and the aforementioned continuums?

Originally the Franks were not an ethnic group per se, but rather a group of Germanic tribes or maybe rather a tribal confederation that lived in an area on the right side of the Rhine stretching roughly from the Lahn to the IJsselmeer during late antiquity.
It seems that *frank most likely meant “free” and “brave” in proto-West Germanic and that it was derived from proto-Germanic *frankaz (which could also have been borrowed into proto-Finnic and become Finnish rankka, which means “arduous”, “tough”, “intense”, “harsh”, and “rough”; also compare to the Finnish word for a Frank, Frankki), which seems to have meant ”fierce”, “wild”, and “made to be ‘wild'”, i.e. ”made to be thrown”. It also seems that the word *frankô (“javelin”) was derived from a longer word for javelin via the javelin part of the term (seemingly most likely *gaizaz) becoming omitted, and that the term for a brave and/or free-spirited person would have been simplified in a similar fashion and obviously later become the ethnonym *Franko.

Little by little, the Frankish tribes formed a more cohesive group with an increasingly significant common identity, which over time turned into their new ethnic identity. The first time they were united under one ruler was under the first Merovingian king, Clovis I. They then expanded this Frankish Kingdom greatly under the rule of the Merovingian dynasty, also becoming gradually more Romanized in the process. During the last century of Merovingian rule the power of the kings had been greatly reduced, and the kingdom was in practice controlled by the mayors of the palace, the most notable of whom was Charles Martel, who also held the title of Duke and Prince of the Franks and whose second son Pepin the Short became the first Carolingian king. Forces under Martel’s command defeated the invading forces of the Umayyad Caliphate at the Battle of Tours, and the Franks later expelled the last of the Umayyads from their territory with the assistance of the Lombards. Under the rule of Pepin’s son Charlemagne, the Franks conquered the Lombards, 26 years after which he was crowned Emperor of the Romans by the pope. The territory of the empire ended up getting divided into West Francia, Middle Francia and East Francia between the surviving sons of his son Louis the Pious.

As there would still seem to be a relatively strong need to process the history of the Germans, it seems fairly appropriate to focus mostly on it hereinafter: West Francia obviously became France, East Francia eventually absorbed the northern parts of Middle Francia and came to be known as the Kingdom of Germany, and the other parts of Middle Francia became the Kingdom of Burgundy and the Kingdom of Italy. The Kingdom of Germany was the core of the Holy Roman Empire, which was ultimately dissolved by emperor Francis II roughly eight months after its forces had suffered a crushing defeat against Napoleon’s army in the Battle of Austerlitz. This dissolution also happened to take place 1005 years after Charlemagne was crowned Emperor of the Romans; this coronation is seen by some as the establishment of the HRE (which is also sometimes referred to as the First Reich), but it seems more reasonable to consider the coronation of Otto I as emperor after a 38-year period without an emperor as the proper founding of the HRE and thus to think that it lasted for 844 years.

Over time, the Frankish language too became divided, and a number of languages that descend at least partially from it are still spoken: Old Low Franconian evolved into Dutch (and thus also into Afrikaans, of course), and the highland dialects of Frankish evolved into the Franconian dialects of Old High German, which along with the other dialects of Old High German evolved into the various dialects of Middle High German, which in turn evolved into, for example, Luxembourgish, Yiddish, Austro-Bavarian, and Standard German, of which the first two are based on Franconian dialects; Standard German is primarily based on East Central and Eastern Upper German dialects.

After the Napoleonic wars the most significant states that controlled parts of the former territory of the HRE were the Austrian Empire and the Kingdom of Prussia. As is well known, Prussia later became the driving force in the establishment of the North German Confederation and its transition into the German Empire aka. the Second Reich, the demise of which following its defeat in World War I obviously led to a period of history the aftermath of which defines Europe to a large degree to this day. Even though a lot of time has passed since then, and things seem to have somewhat improved in Europe during said time, many people still appear to have at least some issues related to that period of German history they arguably shouldn’t, and as such it seems appropriate to try and address said issues in some fashion:

Considering the history of the Germans in its entirety, it would seem to be quite reasonable to conclude that it doesn’t appear to be very sensible to judge them primarily by the period of it that is overwhelmingly defined by the horrific consequences of Prussian militarism, which, of course, includes the rise and rule of the National Socialist German Workers’ Party. The national socialist regime was obviously immensely devastating and exceptionally appalling, but why should people who were in no way responsible for its actions be made to suffer in any way because of the actions of the Nazi regime if they don’t enjoy some lasting benefit as a result of said actions? It would seem reasonable to argue that the German people as a collective didn’t gain a net benefit as a result of the actions of the Nazi regime and that they should therefore not be subjected to further collective punishment because of said actions.

A lifetime has passed since the dissolution of the Third Reich, and a lifetime should arguably be a long enough time from said dissolution for people to be able to see the history of the Germans clearly and to put things into proper perspective; all things considered, having a habit of excessively emphasizing or an obsession of some kind with the parts or a part of German history characterized by totalitarianism seems rather bizarre and unhealthy, but unfortunately indoctrination and trauma-induced issues frequently die hard and sadly often only with the recipients thereof and the traumatized, respectively, of course.

A conspicuously dark cloud and the long-term issues it created

This is obviously a relatively sombre topic to start with, but a blog has to start with something, and this might as well be it, considering that it would appear to be best if I wrote about the matters mentioned in this entry and also preferably sooner than later:
It seems to me that a great number of people have found and still find it fairly difficult to fully cope with the idea of democide, especially of the industrialized kind, and the democides carried out by Nazi Germany and its collaborators would appear to be the most problematic in this way.

It can be especially overwhelming to think about such events if one does not truly understand what kinds of misguided ideas led to them, and I don’t think it is very shameful to admit it if one doesn’t: admission of ignorance and confusion is the first step toward true comprehension, and the inability to do so is a far greater shame than incomprehension in itself can ever be, obviously especially if such a crippling personality defect is refractory.

It is fairly typical of me and perhaps even most people to try to find at least thin silver linings even to the darkest clouds as a way to cope or attempt to cope; I think the only effects of the atrocities committed by the Nazi regime and its collaborators I could ever describe as positive were the instillation of an increased awareness of the dangers of incomprehension, disinformation, collective narcissism, misdirected hatred, and totalitarianism in at least most of the groups targeted by the National Socialist German Workers’ Party, a very large number of Europeans, and people of European heritage in particular plus as a more indirect effect the especially significant one that fortunately still benefits the group the destruction of which the Nazi regime prioritized, i.e. the Jewish people, of course, and which obviously was the refoundation of their own sovereign state, an incredibly exceptionally bittersweet realization of the hopes and dreams of many generations of Jews, and said state is clearly a fairly durable wellspring of hope for them, at least for the time being.

I hope that we can one day help all of the peoples in the West Asian region by strictly and decisively, but always clearly rationally and justly enforcing a real and lasting peace by whatever means necessary and thus hopefully catalyze the start of a new, more enlightened era of thriving civilization(s) in the region, the peoples of which we Europeans are actually fairly closely related to.
I am reasonably confident that given a relatively high level of security, durable stability, universal proper education, and a sufficient amount of at the very least relatively decent economic opportunities, the peoples of the region just might in time go through their own renaissance periods of various kinds and lengths and come to understand that it is in our mutual interest to forge lasting partnerships, especially considering the scope and difficulty of the challenges facing us all in the foreseeable future.

The most critical prerequisite for the kind of peace described above and its desired consequences would seem to be an enduring just settlement of the Palestinian issue, for which I think I have devised a solution that might actually work as intended if the terms of the treaty are effectively and dispassionately, i.e. very professionally enforced.

I will present my detailed suggestions later this year.